Visual Semiotics in car advertisements

(2000)1462

Visual semiotics
The feasibility of such a domain as visual semiotics, a speciality purportedly
concerned with the investigation of all kinds of meaning conveyed by means of
the visual senses, may well be doubted: following one common interpretation,
it should be excluded by the structuralist conception according to which form,
not substance, is relevant to meaning. Yet, Saussure’s preoccupation with the
linearity of speech, as against the multidimensionality of pictures, Jakobson’s
interest in the differences between auditory and visual signs, and, more
generally, the Prague school model, according to which the receiver of the work
of art is called upon to transform a sign into a concrete perceptual object,
certainly suggest a different conception. Indeed,
Lessing already was
essentially concerned with the location of visual signs in space, as opposed to
the projection of auditory signs into time. According to the Greimas school,
however, all meaning is of a kind, so not only do pictures and literature
manifest the same organising principles, but, more broadly, visuality and
aurality must be taken to be identical on a deeper level.
In recent semiotics, Kümmel (1969) has written a rather haphazard
catalogue of visually conveyed signs. The first to propound a division of all

signs according to the sense modalities which they address was Thomas Sebeok
(1976). Preziosi (1983) then ranged architecture among the several devices of
visual communication, opposing them in some respects to verbal language.
According to Fernande Saint-Martin (1987), visual semiotics comprises the
study of pictorial art, sculpture, and architecture. This means that she ignores
all visual signs which are not, in our culture, considered to be artistic (in spite
of some passing remarks on children’s drawings in other publications). In
actual fact, pictures, sculpture and architecture also are the only domains, with
an emphasis on the first one, which are covered by Groupe µ’s (1992) recent
book the title of which announces that it is concerned with visual signs.
Like Preziosi, Saint-Martin opposes visual semiosis to the verbal kind,
forgetting that verbal language may alternatively be conveyed by writing,
which can be rudimentary, as in the case of alphabetical script, or more
elaborate, as in the various kinds of ideographic writing, in some varieties of
logotypes and pictograms, and in gestural emblems. The issue is further
complicated by the fact that many types of semiosis are partly visual, and
partly conveyed by other senses, as, for instance, theatre, the cinema, dance,
and even food and clothing. Indeed, if the gaze, as has often been suggested, is
really privileged in Occidental (or even pan-human) culture, the wider semiotic
domain of the “natural world” will be largely dissolved into visual semiotics.


To the extent that pictorial semiotics has been well-advised to turn
recently to perceptual psychology in search of its foundations, we must
suppose there to be some general organising principles of pictorial and other
visual signs which are relevant to their transmission of meaning. If so, however,
it will be necessary to distinguish those domains which are intrinsically visual
in organisation, from those in which meanings which are differently constituted
are merely secondarily conveyed by visual means.
On the other hand, from the point of view of Hjelmslevean semiotics,
we would normally not expect visuality, being a mere “substance” or even
“matter”, to determine any relevant categorisations of semiotic means. In their
dictionary, Greimas & Courtés actually claims that sense modalities, identified
with the expression substance, are not pertinent for semiotics, and this is no
doubt the reason for visuality being one of the many layers between the unique
picture and signification per se being left out of consideration in Floch’s
analyses.
This type of argument is based on a confusion of the terms “substance”
and “matière”, as employed by Hjelmslev, and in their ordinary usage. In fact,
the term “matière”, to Hjelmslev, is that which is unknowable, and, as a
consequence, not susceptible of being analysed; that is, it is the residue of the

analysis; and “substance”, which, in the earlier texts, is the term used for
“matière” in the above-mentioned sense, stands, in the later works, for the
combination of “matière” and “form”. Thus, “substance”, in the early works,
and “matter” later, simply means “that which is not pertinent relative to the
other plane of the sign” (see discussion in Sonesson 1989,II.4. and 1988); it does
not necessarily stand for matter in the sense of ordinary language, that is, the
material of which something is made, or the sense modality. If the material or
the sense modality turns out to be relevant in relation to the other plane of
signification, it becomes form (from Hjelmslev’s standpoint, this is what
happens in connotational language).
More importantly, the psychology of perception certainly seems to suggest
the existence of some common organisation which puts all or most visually
conveyed meanings on the same level. If all signs must also be objects of
perception, there is every reason to believe that the modality according to
which they are perceived determine at least part of their nature. This is indeed
the position taken by Groupe µ (1992: 58f), who goes on to compare this
conception to the one favoured by such linguists as Saussure, Martinet, and
Bloomfield, according to which the vocal character of language is one of its
defining characteristics. More to the point, they observe that the linearity of
verbal language is a constraint imposed on linguistic form by the characteristics


of the vocal channel by which it was once exclusively conveyed. That is, the
qualities of the visual sense modality are of interest to semiotics, to the extent
that they specify formal properties embodied in each system addressed to that
particular sense. Although Groupe µ seems unaware of it, Hjelmslev (1953)
does not reason differently when he posits different “forms” for written and
spoken language.
If, however, properties imposed by their mode of communication are only
some among several traits defining these signs, as is the case of the linearity of
verbal language, one may well wonder whether we are really justified in
making visuality into a subdivision of semiotics. There may, moreover, be
other, perhaps more fundamental division blocks of semiosis, of which pictures
and some other visual signs form a part, such as, for instance, that of iconicity.
On the other hand, it is conceivable that some more decisive argument could be
advanced for privileging the domain of visuality over other possible divisions.
But to the extent that there is a legitimate domain of visual semiotics, it
should comprehend much more the sacred trinity of art history, painting (to
which drawing, photography, and so on, have been assimilated), sculpture, and
architecture, of which Groupe µ, just like Saint-Martin (1987) seems to be the
victim, in spite of the promise made in the introduction (p.12ff) to ignore

received categories such as art. As soon as we leave the traditional divisions of
art history behind, this analysis has a very limited value. Thus, sculpture
should be compared semiotically similar objects like the tailor’s dummy, and the
like. At one point (p.405f), the authors are suddenly reminded of marionettes,
considered as a kind of sculpture to which movement has been added. But why
not also add the ballet dancer, whose art is certainly visual?
There are also significations which are only partly visual, such as those of
theatre communication. Others might be considered not to have an intrinsically
visual organisation, such as writing, the conformation of which depends in part
on spoken language. But all kinds of gestures and bodily postures, objects,
dummies, logotypes, clothing, and many other phenomena must be counted as
visual signs and significations. In fact, even visual perception per se supposes a
pick-up of meaning of sorts. Not only should we therefore have to face the
arduous task of determining the ways in which the various kinds of visual
semiosis, beyond those of pictures, architecture, and sculpture differ, but it also
remains to be shown that they all have sufficient properties in common to be
considered “visual signs” And we have to determine in which way pictures
differ from other, intrinsically visual signs, not only from sculpture and
architecture. The domain of visual semiotics, to the extent that it exists, remains
to be constituted.


The real issues of visual semiotics may then turn out to be still, or rather
again, those characterised by Lessing (cf. Sonesson 1988): if language is better
adapted to the rendering of temporal succession, while pictures lend
themselves more readily to deployment in space, then how is that visuality and
narrativity, as many critics of television and more recent media have suggested,
concurrently invade our culture? The interrelations of visual and auditory signs
(which are not simply verbal either) certainly deserves more serious
consideration than has been given them by those propounding the domain of
visual semiotics.
Göran Sonesson

Bibliography:
Kümmel, Peter, Struktur und Funktion sichtbarer Zeichen Quickborn. Schnelle
1969
Greimas, A.J. & Corutés, J., Sémiotique. Dictionnaire raiaonné de la théorie du
langage. Paris: Hachette 1979.
Groupe µ, Traité du signe visuel. Paris: Seuil 1992.
Hjelmslev, Louis, Introduction à la discusssion générale des problèmes relatifs
à la phonologie de langues mortes. In Acta Congressus Madvigiani: Proceedings

of the Second International Congress of Classical Studies, Copenhagen 1954,
Copenhagen 1954, 101-113.
Jakobson, Roman, On the relation between visual and auditory signs. In
Selected Writings II, 338-344. Paris & The Hague: Mouton 1967.
Preziosi, Donald, Advantages and limitations of visual communication, in
Krampen, M., ed. Visuelle Kommunikation und/oder verbale Kommunikation.
Berlin: Olms Verlag, Hildesheim/Hochschule der Künste 1983, 1-34.
Saint-Martin, Fernande, Sémiologie du langage visuel. Québec: Presse de l
´Université du Québec 1987.
Sebeok, Thomas A., Contributions to the doctrine of signs. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
Sonesson, Göran, Methods and models in pictorial semiotics. Lund: Institute of Art
History 1988.
Sonesson, Göran, Pictorial concepts. Lund: Lund University Press 1989.
See also Icon, Iconicity, Image/Picture

Dokumen yang terkait

Analisis Komparasi Internet Financial Local Government Reporting Pada Website Resmi Kabupaten dan Kota di Jawa Timur The Comparison Analysis of Internet Financial Local Government Reporting on Official Website of Regency and City in East Java

19 819 7

ANTARA IDEALISME DAN KENYATAAN: KEBIJAKAN PENDIDIKAN TIONGHOA PERANAKAN DI SURABAYA PADA MASA PENDUDUKAN JEPANG TAHUN 1942-1945 Between Idealism and Reality: Education Policy of Chinese in Surabaya in the Japanese Era at 1942-1945)

1 29 9

Implementasi Prinsip-Prinsip Good Corporate Governance pada PT. Mitra Tani Dua Tujuh (The Implementation of the Principles of Good Coporate Governance in Mitra Tani Dua Tujuh_

0 45 8

Improving the Eighth Year Students' Tense Achievement and Active Participation by Giving Positive Reinforcement at SMPN 1 Silo in the 2013/2014 Academic Year

7 202 3

An Analysis of illocutionary acts in Sherlock Holmes movie

27 148 96

The Effectiveness of Computer-Assisted Language Learning in Teaching Past Tense to the Tenth Grade Students of SMAN 5 Tangerang Selatan

4 116 138

The correlation between listening skill and pronunciation accuracy : a case study in the firt year of smk vocation higt school pupita bangsa ciputat school year 2005-2006

9 128 37

Existentialism of Jack in David Fincher’s Fight Club Film

5 71 55

Perancangan Sistem Informasi Akuntansi Laporan Keuangan Arus Kas Pada PT. Tiki Jalur Nugraha Ekakurir Cabang Bandung Dengan Menggunakan Software Microsoft Visual Basic 6.0 Dan SQL Server 2000 Berbasis Client Server

32 174 203

Phase response analysis during in vivo l 001

2 30 2