THE UNION OF MIND AND BODY IN THE CARTESIAN DUALISM

24.1.2008 [39-55]

THE UNION OF MIND AND
BODY IN THE CARTESIAN
DUALISM
Armada Riyanto

STFT Widya Sasana, Malang, Indonesia

ABSTRACT
Dalam disiplin ilmu filsafat sejak Yunani Awali, manusia
dimengerti sebagai terdiri dari badan dan jiwa. Bagi
Sokrates manusia adalah jiwa-nya. Sebab, badan tidak
menampilkan kodrat kemanusiawian yang sesungguhnya.
Plato melanjutkan Sokrates dengan “menyangkal”
kepentingan keberadaan badan. Problem filosofis klasik
itu berlanjut pada pemikiran René Descartes yang
menyatakan bahwa badan adalah res extensa (itu yang
memiliki keluasan), sementara jiwa res cogitans (itu yang
berpikir). Karena itu, dalam Descartes istilah yang lebih
tepat untuk jiwa adalah “mind” daripada “soul”. Tetapi

soal paling krusial dari definisi ini ialah bagaimana
mungkin yang material bersatu sedemikian rupa dengan
res cogitans sehingga menyusun sebuah kesatuan tunggal
eksistensi manusia yang begitu memesona? Pertanyaan
inilah yang menjadi status questionis dari artikel ini.

39

Armada Riyanto: The Union Of Mind And Body

Key Words:
lMind lBody lHuman Being lUnion lDualism lEns per- se
and ens per accidens

T

he crucial problem in Descartes' concept of human being could
be formulated as follows: How two really distinct things, mind and
body, can somehow generate another thing, human being, which is itself a
unity, that is, a genuine individual or an ens per se. By ens per se Descartes

means a substance. In Aristotle substance is linked to the composition of
form and matter. Form is a substance, while matter is an accident. In
Thomas Aquinas, ens per se cannot have a plurality of actual constituents.
The contrary of an ens per se is ens per accidens, that is, if the union is accidental
to at least one of the components.
Here, what I want to elaborate is whether there is in Descartes'
philosophy a notion of the union of mind and body which gives a
satisfactory account of the unity of human being, an account according to
which a human being has an intuitive claim being one thing, and not merely
two things conjoined. Or, whether in Descartes the unity of human being is
understood as ens per se or ens per accidens. If the union of body is ens per se, it
follows that a human being is a genuine individual.1
That Descartes considers a human being to be a genuine individual is
an underappreciated fact among commentators. To take an extreme case, in
a recent article, Fred Sommers alleges that "a Cartesian person is a nonindividual, since it is composed of a mind and a body," and he leaves the
impression that it is Descartes' intention to characterize human beings as
non-individuals.2 Etienne Gilson also asserts that because of the distinction
between mind and body Descartes has a difficulty to explain human's
individuality. He says that "Medieval philosophy distinguished the body
and soul less really than Descartes, in that they did not make two complete

substances, and this is why they had less difficulty than Descartes in uniting
them."3
Human's Composition of Body and Mind
Many philosophers believe that human is a being composed of mind
and body. This view involves two claims. One is that mind is something

40

MELINTAS 24.1.2008

distinct from the body. The other is that the mind and the body form a unity
which is a human. Some philosophers have emphasized the former claim,
while others have emphasized the latter.
Plato and Augustine emphasized the distinction between soul and
body. That the soul is something distinct from the body, they believed to be
apparent from the fact that what the soul knows best, it knows without the
aid of any bodily operations. If the soul can know without the aid of the
body, then the soul is neither a part nor an aspect of the body. On the
contrary, it is an incorporeal thing, which is independent of and thus
separable from the body.

On the other hand, Aristotle and Aquinas insisted upon the unity of
human, because otherwise phenomena such as sensation and voluntary
movement, which involve the operation of both soul and body, could not
be explained. They reconciled the dualism of soul and body to the unity of
man by saying that the body and the soul are united as matter (materi) to
form (forma). The soul, as the substantial form of the body, is what makes
the body an actually living organism.
One who adopts the theory that the soul and the body are independent
entities is faced with the task of explaining the phenomena which make the
unity of man plausible. Augustine explained the phenomena of sensation
and voluntary movement in terms of the soul's action upon the body.
According to his conception of the causal situation, the inferior cannot act
upon the superior. Thus, if two unequal things are in a causal relation, the
cause is the one which is superior and the effect the one which is inferior.
The superiority of one thing is judge on the basis of its relative simplicity.
Since the soul is simpler than the body, it is superior to the body. Thus, in all
cases in which the soul and the body are in a causal relation, it is the soul
which acts upon the body. This includes the case of sensation, for sensation
occurs only when the soul "directs the sense to the sensible thing and keeps
the vision itself fixed upon it.4”

Descartes' Dualism
Like Plato and Augustine, Descartes emphasizes the dualism of mind
and body. If matter or body is not something really distinct from mind, then
the new science, which offers only mechanistic explanations, would not give

41

Armada Riyanto: The Union Of Mind And Body

an exhaustive account of the physical world. Similarly, if the mind were not
something really distinct from matter, then the religious doctrine of
personal immortality would be untenable.5 By mind Descartes means that
which corresponds to the power of knowing that everyone has.
The power of knowing, according to its various functions, is
sometimes called pure understanding, sometimes imagination,
sometimes memory, sometimes sensation; but, properly speaking, it
is called mind when it forms new ideas in the imagination [phantasia],
or when it applies itself to those which are already traced there.6

The body is defined as that which is different from mind.

I conceive fully what a body is (that is, I conceive body as a
complete thing), when I think only that it is a thing, which is
extended, shaped, mobile, etc., while I deny of it all the things which
belong to the nature of mind.7

Descartes even emphasizes that body is the substance that immediately
presupposes extension, like shape, local movement. It could be seen in
these statements:
The substance which is immediately the subject of extension
and of the accidents which presuppose extension, like shape,
position, local movement, etc., is called Body.8

The body is corporeal substance which is related to the local extension:
There are certain acts which we call corporeal, like size, shape,
motion, and all the other things which cannot be conceived without
local extension, and we call by the name body the substance in which
they reside.9

That the body is the corporeal substance is evident by itself:
If it is said, for example, that a body is a corporeal substance, without


42

MELINTAS 24.1.2008

at the same time defining what a corporeal substance is, these two
words, corporeal substance, will not make us in any way more
knowledgeable than the word body.10

Therefore, the body is divisible:
Being extended, divisible, of a given shape, etc., are the forms or
the attributes by means of which I know that substance which is
called body.11

It is God who makes body of man. God makes it from earth. The body is
something like statue or machine.
I suppose (in this Treatise) that the body is nothing other than a
statue or machine made of earth, which God forms expressly.12

Descartes believes that function of the body coincides with its laws laid

down by God him self.
God has made our body as a machine and has willed that it
functions as a universal instrument; operating always in the same
manner according to its own laws.13

Descartes states that mind and body is different. Their difference is
great so as to create the rough dualism of mind and body. They differ to
each other by nature. By saying nature Descartes would means that such
difference is created by God.
There is a great difference between the mind and the body, in
that the body, by nature, is always divisible, and the mind is entirely
indivisible.14

Even the mind is not influenced by the corporeal substance:
The mind does not receive impressions from all parts of the
body immediately, but only from the brain, or perhaps even from one
of its smallest parts [i.e., the pineal gland].15

43


Armada Riyanto: The Union Of Mind And Body

In this following statement, assertively Descartes says that the mind is
not body. This statement seems to be tautology, but it indicates that
Descartes really distinguishes or separates body and mind in man.
Everything which can think is mind or is called mind. But, because
body and mind are really distinct, that which is not body is mind.16

Descartes claims that he is the first man who elaborates this
understanding:
No one before me, as far as I know, asserted that mind
consisted in one thing alone, namely the faculty of thinking and the
inward source [of “thinkind”].17

According to Descartes' doctrine of the real distinction between mind
and body, it is not merely the case that the mind and the body can exist apart.
They are two substances which have entirely different natures. The nature
of the body is extension and the nature of the mind thought, and there is
nothing at all common to thought and extension. The mind and the body
are not capable of the same sorts of modifications. The mind is capable

only of modifications of thought, and the body only of modifications of
extension.
Like Augustine, Descartes seeks to explain the phenomena which
make the unity of man plausible, by appealing to the notion of causal
influence. In order to explain sense experience Descartes maintains that the
body has causal influence upon the mind. In order to explain such
phenomena as memory, imagination and voluntary movement, he
maintains that the mind has causal influence upon the body.
For the Augustinian principle that the inferior cannot act upon the
superior, Descartes substitutes the principle, manifest by natural light, that
the cause must be adequate to the effect. The sense in which the cause must
be adequate to its effect is expressed in two ways: The first axiom is
"whatever reality or perfection exists in a thing exists formally or else
eminently in its first and adequate cause."18 Regarding the first axiom he
says more clearly in the following excerpt:

44

MELINTAS 24.1.2008


That there is nothing in the effect, that has not existed in a
similar or in some higher form in the cause, is a first principle than
which none clearer can be entertained. The common truth 'from
nothing, nothing comes' is identical with it. For, if we allow that there
is something in the effect which did not exist in the cause, we must
grant also that this something has been created from nothing; again
the only reason why nothing cannot be the cause of a thing, is that in
such a cause there would not be the same thing as existed in the
19
effect.

The second axiom is said in the Third Meditation: "Now it is manifest
by the natural light that there must at least be as much reality in the efficient
and total cause as in its effect." Like the first axiom, this axiom or statement
is based upon the principle that something cannot come from nothing.
What is produced in the effect must first exist in the cause. If the cause
produced something in the effect which it did not first possess in itself and
communicate to the effect, that thing would be produced from nothing.
Thus, the cause must contain in itself so as to bring about in the effect. In
order that the cause may contain in itself what it brings about in the effect,
the cause and the effect must have something in common.
The Questions of Descartes' Dualism
The problem begins with the question of Gassendi with regards to the
Meditations: How can the soul move the body, if the soul is not material, and
how can it receive species of corporeal objects? Descartes answers that "the
perplexity involved in these questions arises entirely from a false
supposition that can by no manner of means be proved, namely, that if the
soul and body are two substances of diverse nature that prevents them from
being capable of acting on one another."20 This answer, however, is clearly
unsatisfactory. For, as Descartes himself sees the causal situation, one
substance cannot produce a modification in another substance which is of
an entirely different nature.
Besides Gassendi's question, in her letter of May 6/16 and June 10/20,
1643, Princess Elizabeth asked Descartes how mind thinking and
unextended, could interact with body, extended and unthinking. In his
response Descartes appeals to the "primitive" notion of the union of mind

45

Armada Riyanto: The Union Of Mind And Body

and body. Descartes says:
First I observe that there are in us certain primitive notions which are
as it were models on which all our other knowledge is patterned.
There are very few such notions. First, there are the most general
ones, such as being, number, and duration, which apply to everything
we can conceive. Then, as regards body in particular, we have only
the notion of extension which entails the notions of shape and
motion; and as regards soul in particular we have only the notion of
thought, which includes the conceptions of the intellect and the
inclinations of the will. Finally, as regards soul and body together, we
have only the notion of their union, on which depends our notion of
the soul's power to move the body, and the body's power to act on the
soul and cause sensations and passions.21

Descartes tries to accommodate his principle that the cause must be
adequate to the effect, by de-emphasizing his doctrine of the complete
disparity between mind and body. The mind can cause changes in the body,
and the body can cause changes in the mind, by virtue of the substantial
union of mind and body.
Thus, Descartes' notion of the union of mind and body arises in
response to the problem of how the mind and the body can causally
interact. Or, if two substances have different natures, how can there be a
union of these substances which is itself a simple nature?
Descartes' Belief of The Unity of Human Being
Descartes, however, belives that a human being is a unity. In this
excerpt he gives a decisive example of how he himself unites with his own
body:
Nature teaches me also by the sensations of pain, hunger, thirst, etc.,
that I am not only housed in my body, like a pilot in his ship, but,
besides that, that I am conjoined very tightly and so mixed and
mingled with it, that I compose a single whole with it.22

Even the mind is imprinted in the body:

46

MELINTAS 24.1.2008

The mind, although really distinguished from the body, is
nevertheless joined to it, and is touched by the traces [vestigia] which
are imprinted in it.23

The mind is not only imprinted, but also moves the body. This causal
movement of the body can be seen in the daily experience:
For the fact that the mind, which is incorporeal, can make the
body move, there is neither reasoning nor comparison derived from
other things which could teach us; but experiences which are very
certain and very evident make us recognize it every day.24

Similarly, in the Passions of the Soul he states:
The soul is truly joined to the whole body, and one cannot
properly say that it is in some one of its parts to the exclusion of
others.25

In Article 31, he says that the soul exercises its functions in the body:
Although the soul is joined to the whole body, there is
nevertheless in the body a certain part in which the soul exercises its
functions more particularly than in all the others. And it is usually
believed that this part is the brain, or perhaps the heart.26

It is evident that for Descartes the body is united to the soul, since from
experience when someone talks about the body, it refers to the body of man
united with the soul, not the separated body in itself. This long excerpt can
bring into light such a belief of Descartes:
I find that the word body is quite equivocal; for, when we speak
of a body in general, we understand a determinate part of matter, and
altogether of the quantity of which the universe is composed, so that
one could not take away ever so little from that quantity, without our
judging immediately that the body is smaller, and that it is no longer
whole, nor change any particle of that matter, without our thinking
that the body is no longer totally the same, or numerically the same.
But, when we speak of the body of a man, we do not understand a

47

Armada Riyanto: The Union Of Mind And Body

determinate part of matter, nor one which has a determinate size, but
we merely understand all the matter which is, taken altogether, united
with the soul of that man; in such a way that, even though that matter
changes, and even though its quantity increases or diminishes, we still
believe that it is the same body, numerically the same, as long as it
remains joined and substantially united to the same soul.27

Again, he gives a decisive account of the unity of body and soul. He
states that the soul is truly joined to the body:
The soul is truly joined to all the body, and it cannot be properly
said to be in some one of these parts to the exclusion of the others,
because the body is one, and in some fashion indivisible, because of
the placement of its organs, which are all so related to one another
that when one of them is taken away, that makes the whole body
defective; and because the soul is of a nature which has no reference
to extension, nor to dimensions, or other properties of the matter of
which the body is composed, but simply to the whole union of its
organs.28

It is certainly true that Descartes emphasizes the real distinction
between mind and body much more than the unity of a human being. He
admits as much in a letter to Princess Elizabeth and gives a hint as to why:
There are two facts about the human soul on which depend all
the things we can know of its nature. The first is that it thinks, the
second is that it is united to the body and can act and be acted upon
along with it. About the second I have said hardly anything; I have
tried only to make the first well understood. For my principal aim
was to prove the distinction between soul and body, and to this end
only the first was useful, and the second might have been harmful.29

In another letter, this time to Regius, he makes a very similar remark:
Many people make the mistake of thinking that the soul is not
really distinct from the body than make the mistake of admitting
their distinction and denying their substantial union, and in order to
refute those who believe souls to be mortal it is more important to

48

MELINTAS 24.1.2008

teach the distinction of parts in man than to teach their union.30

But to teach the distinction between mind and body is not to deny their
union. Earlier in the same letter to Regius, Descartes advises him to say that
he believes a human being is a true ens per se:
And whenever the occasion arises, in public and in private, you
should give out that you believe that a human being is a true ens per se,
and not ens per accidens, and that the mind and the body are united in a
real and substantial manner. You must say that they are united not by
position or disposition, as you say in your last paper -- for this too is
open to objection and, in my opinion, quite untrue -- but by a true
mode of union, as everyone agrees, though nobody explains what
this means and so you need not do so either.31.

These three passages from the letters to Princess Elizabeth and Regius
give clear indication that Descartes does not call into question the
Aristotelian and common view that a human being is a genuine unity, that is,
an individual. There is other important evidence that Descartes believes a
human being is an individual. In the Sixth Meditation he asserts that he is not
united to his body as a pilot to a ship, but is "closely joined and, as it were,
mixed together with it, so that I make up one thing with it."32 Moreover,
there are several passages in which he refers to the substantial union of
mind and body (some are already mentioned above). By using the
expression "substantial union" I take him to be pointing out not merely that
the union is a union of two substances, which he does think is the case, but
that the product of the union is itself a substance. Descartes uses the terms
"substance", ens per se, and "complete thing interchangeably, and all of them
I take to be equivalent to my terms "individual" and "genuine unity."
There is a standard picture of the Cartesian created universe which
perhaps contributes to the tendency to deny that Descartes conceives of a
human being as a genuine individual. According to this picture, the
Cartesian created universe is populated by a lot of minds, but only one
extended substance, the entire extended world, of which individual bodies
are merely modes.

49

Armada Riyanto: The Union Of Mind And Body

We do not form two ideas in our imagination, one of body, and
the other of extension, but a single idea, that of an extended body.33

Such a picture makes it difficult to see how a human being could be a
genuine individual. How could a substance, in this case a mind, be
combined with a mode of another substance, in this case a human body, to
form a genuine unity?
Martial Gueroult ascribes to Descartes a very strong notion of what it
is to be a created substance in the strict sense, according to which only God
can cause substances to come into or to go out of existence, and according
to which substances can go out of existence only by annihilation.34 The key
evidence in favor of Gueroult's interpretation is a famous passage from the
Synopsis of the Meditations:
First, it must be known that absolutely all substances or things
which must be created by God in order to exist, are by their nature
incorruptible, nor can they ever cease to be unless they are reduced
to nothing by God denying them His concurrence, and second, it
must be noted that body, at least taken generally, is a substance and
for that reason never perishes. But the human body differs from
other bodies only insofar as it is composed of a certain configuration
of members and other such accidents; while the human mind is not
similarly composed out of any accidents, but is a pure substance; for
although all its accidents are changed, so that it understands other
things, wills others, senses others, etc., the mind does not for that
reason become something else; however, the human body becomes
something else from the sole fact that the shape of some one of its
parts is changed; from which it follows that body very easily ceases to
exist, whereas the mind by its nature is immortal.35

In the Synopsis passage quoted above, Descartes suggests that entities
which satisfy the conditions of the strong conception of created substance
are not composed of parts or other similar accidents. Following his
language in that passage, we can refer to such substances as pure substances.
But even though bodies are composed of parts and so fall short of being
pure substances -- we might call them impure substances -- they
nevertheless should still be considered as full-fledged substances.

50

MELINTAS 24.1.2008

Therefore, contrary to the standard picture of the Cartesian created
universe, Descartes, in constructing a human being, does not face the
impossible task of generating a unity out of a substance and a mode of
another substance. His task, which may seem equally impossible, is that of
generating a unity out of two substances.
It is clear that the issue as to whether Descartes' human being can claim
to be a unity is not whether it satisfies the conditions of the strong
conception of reated substance. Accordingly, I am not referring to the
strong conception when I say that he uses the term "substance" to mean a
unity. Descartes thinks the substantial union of mind and body is
incomprehensible from the point of view of our finite intellects, even
though it is an indubitable fact made known by sensation and made possible
by God's omnipotence.
Descartes could propose that a union of things generates a per se unity
when that union is not accidental to at least one of the components. This
would entail that a human being is an ens per se, provided that a human being
is understood to be a composite of a mind and a human body, as opposed to
being a composite of a mind and a determinate part of matter.
If the human body cannot exist without being united to the mind, it
would seem to follow by his own criteria that mind and body are only
modally distinct. I have argued elsewhere, however, that hi account of real
distinction does not require that mind and body can each exist out of real
union with the other. Instead, what he does require for real distinction,
namely, that each can exist without having the essential attribute of the
other existing in it, is consistent with the claim that the body must be united
to the mind in order to exist.
In a letter of December 1641, in which he is again coaching Regius,
under fire for asserting that a human being is an ens per accidens, he advises
him to say that it is not absolutely accidental to the mind that it be united to
the body or to the body that it be united to the mind, and tells him not to
deny that it is only due to a miracle that they can exist apart.
It may be objected that it is not accidental to the human body
that it should be conjoined to the soul, but its very nature, since,
when a body has all the dispositions required to receive the soul,

51

Armada Riyanto: The Union Of Mind And Body

without which it is not a human body, it cannot, without a miracle, be
that the soul is not united to it. Moreover, it may be objected that it is
not accidental to the soul that it should be joined to the body, but it is
only accidental to it that it should be separated from the body after
death. All of this should not be denied, lest the theologians be
offended again, but nevertheless, it ought to be responded that these
things can on this account be said to be accidental, that considering
the body alone, we clearly perceive nothing in it on account of which
it demands to be united to the soul, as we perceive nothing in the soul
on account of which it must be united to the body, which is why I
said above that it is in a certain manner accidental, not that it is
absolutely accidental.36

The other response to the objection that Descartes' human being is not
an ens per se is found in the same letter to Regius. He advises Regius to say that
something can be both an ens per se and an ens per accidens:
That which is an ens per se can be made per accidens, for mice are
generated or made by accident from dirt, and yet are entia per se.37

A human being is an ens per se because
Body and soul, in relation to the whole human, are incomplete
substances, and it follows from their being incomplete that what they
constitute is an ens per se.38

A human being is an ens per accidens because
Considering the body alone, we clearly perceive nothing in it on
account of which it demands to be united to the soul, as we perceive
nothing in the soul on account of which it must be united to the
body, which is why I said above that it is in a certain manner
accidental, not that it is absolutely accidental.39

Conclusion
It is undeniable that Descartes sometimes mentions that body and
mind are united, and sometimes emphasizes that human being consists of

52

Armada Riyanto: The Union Of Mind And Body

mind and body. Descartes' view of the union of body and mind is obscure.40
For example after a year he wrote to Regius that "the mind and the body are
united in a real and substantial manner,"41 he said, "We affirm that a human
being is made up of body and soul."42
Therefore, the union of body and mind which constitutes a human
being as a substance, in Descartes, cannot be concluded evidently as or an
ens per se or an ens per accidens. We should remember that Descartes applies
both ens per se and ens per accidens to the union of body and mind in human
being. Human being is in one sense ens per se and in another sense an ens per
accidens. By stating this, Descartes seems simply to avoid controversy. In
Replies to the Forth Objections he asserts that a hand is both complete, when
considered by itself, and incomplete, when referred to the whole body of
which it a part, and he uses this example as an analogy to illustrate how mind
and body are at once complete and incomplete.43 However, Descartes'
philosophical account on the union of body and mind becomes a crucial
point which creates a perennial unresolved problem of the mystery of
human being.
End Notes:
1. Cfr.Prof. Gianfranco Basti, Il rapporto mente-corpo nella filosofia e nella
scienza (Bologna: Edizioni Studio Domenicano, 1991). On Chap.
2.2.2. especially on "La soluzione dualista cartesiana del problema
psicofisico".
2. Fred Sommers, "Dualism in Descartes: The Logical Ground," in
Descartes: Critical and Interpretive Essays, ed. Michael Hooker
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978), p. 224.
3. Etienne Gilson's statement is quoted from Paul Hoffman, "The
Unity of Descartes' Man", in The Philosophical Review, XCV, No. 3 (July
1986), p. 341.
4. De Trinitate, XI, 2 (5).
5. Cfr. Daisie Radner, "Descartes' Notion of the Union of Mind and
Body," in Journal of the History of Philosophy 9 (1971), p. 160.
6. Rules, XII. X, 416.
7. Replies, I. IX, 95.
8. Replies, II. IX, 125.
9. Replies, III. IX, 137.

53

MELINTAS 24.1.2008

Search for Truth, X, 517.
Replies IV. IX, 173.
Treatise on Man, XI, 120.
Burman V, 163.
Meditations, VI. IX, 68.
Meditations, VI. IX, 95.
Replies, II. IX, 104.
Notes against a Program, I. VIII 2, 347.
The Philosophical Works of Descartes, trans. Elizabeth S. Haldane and
G.R.T. Ross (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1955),
vol ii, p. 56.
19. Ibid., p. 34-35.
20. Ibid., p. 132.
21. Descartes: Philosophical Letters, ed. Anthony Kenny (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1970), p. 138.
22. Meditations, VI, IX, 64.
23. Letter to "Hyperaspistas," August., 1641. III, 424.
24. Letter to Arnould, July 29, 1648. V, 222.
25. The Philosophical Works of Descartes, translated by Elizabeth S. Haldane
and G.R.T. Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1931) vol.
I, p. 345.
26. Ibid., p. 345.
27. Letter to Mesland, Feb. 9, 1644. IV, 166.
28. Passions, I, 30. XI, 351.
29. Descartes: Philosophical Letters, translation and edited by Anthony
Kenny (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970), p. 137.
30. Ibid., p. 130.
31. Ibid., p. 127.
32. Ibid., p. 192.
33. Rules, XIV. X, 444.
34. See Paul Hoffman, "The unity of Descartes' Man," in The Philosophical
Review, XCV, No. 3 (July 1968), p. 347.
35. The Philosophical Works of Descartes, vol. I, translated by Elizabeth S
Haldane and G.R.T. Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press,
1931) p. 144.
36. Descartes: Philosophical Letters, translated and edited by Anthony Kenny
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970), p. 122.
37. Ibid., p. 122.
38.. Ibid., p. 122.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.

54

MELINTAS 24.1.2008

39. Ibid., p. 122.
40. Cfr. Janet Broughton & Ruth Mattern, "Reinterpreting Descartes o n
the Notion of the Union of Mind and Body," in Journal of the
History of Philosophy 9 (1971), p. 23.
41. Descartes: Philosophical Letters, translated and edited by Anthony
Kenny (OXford: Clarendon Press, 1970), p. 127.
42. Ibid., p. 130.
43. The Philosophical Works of Descartes, translated by Elizabeth S.
Haldane and G.R.T. Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1931), vol. II, 99.
Bibliography:
1. Aquinas, Thomas, De Trinitate, XI, 2 (5).
2. Basti, Gianfranco, Il rapporto mente-corpo nella filosofia e nella scienza
(Bologna: Edizioni Studio Domenicano, 1991).
3. Broughton, Janet & Ruth Mattern, "Reinterpreting Descartes on the
Notion of the Union of Mind and Body," in Journal of the History of
Philosophy 9 (1971).
4. Haldane, Elizabeth S. and G.R.T. Ross (transl.) The Philosophical Works
of Descartes (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1955), vol. II.
5. Hoffman, Paul, "The Unity of Descartes' Man", in The Philosophical
Review, XCV, No. 3 (July 1986).
6. Kenny, Anthony (ed.), Descartes: Philosophical Letters, (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1970).
7. Radner, Daisie, "Descartes' Notion of the Union of Mind and Body,"
in Journal of the History of Philosophy 9 (1971).
8. Sommers, Fred, "Dualism in Descartes: The Logical Ground," in
Descartes: Critical and Interpretive Essays, ed. Michael Hooker (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978).

55