Some properties of communication

M . Colombetti Mathematical Social Sciences 38 1999 171 –196 185 5.3. The system BI 2 The modal system BI is defined by adding to BI the forward fixpoint axiom for 2 1 communication, FF C w . B w ∧ I C w, C a a a and the rule of induction for communication, c . B w ∧ I c a ]]]]] RI . C c . C w a Theorems of BI will still be denoted by £ w. 2 Again, it is easy to check that BI is sound with respect to : FF is true in all 2 C models such that the accessibility relation of C contains the relation defined in the a a previous subsection; and RI is valid if the accessibility relation of C is contained in C a such relation . In Appendix A, I prove that BI is also complete with respect to . a 2 As we should expect, F is a theorem of BI : the implication from left to right is FF , C 2 C and its converse can be proved by RI . The repeated use of FF allows us to derive the C C following theorems: £ C w . B w, a £ C w . B I B w, a a £ C w . B I B I B w, a a a £ . . . . As one can observe, the first theorem states that the main effect the speaker wants to obtain through communication i.e., that w be common belief has been achieved; the second theorem represents the achievement of a Gricean condition i.e., that the intention to obtain the main effect also be common belief; the third theorem represents the achievement of a Strawsonian condition; and the further theorems represent the achievement of analogous conditions, for all higher orders. In the next section, I prove further properties of communication.

6. Some properties of communication

Before proving a few facts about communication, I shall introduce some new terminology. Basically, I define terms to qualify sentences for which certain kinds of theorems can be proved in the logic. The main reason for doing so is to identify a number of concepts that play an important role in the treatment of communication. Let us consider the theorems of the form £ c . B w. E If such a theorem can be proved for given sentences c and w, we can think of c as 186 M . Colombetti Mathematical Social Sciences 38 1999 171 –196 describing an event that makes w evident to all agents. In such a case, I say that c displays w. When c 5w, that is when £ w . B w. E I follow the existing practice and call w public. When w is public, it follows immediately from RI with c 5w that B £ w . B w. Let us now consider the theorems of the form £ w . I w. a If such a theorem can be proved for a given sentence w, I say that w is intentional. Interestingly, when w is intentional we can regard it as describing an action performed by agent a: in fact, actions are basically those propositions for which being intentional is a constitutive property. Therefore, when w .I w is a theorem I shall also say that w a describes an action by a. Finally, I want to define the concept of a communicative act. This is simply an action that implies the communication that w, for some given sentence w. More precisely, c describes a w-communicative act by a if and only if: £ c . I c ∧ C w. a a 6.1. An alternative characterization of communication As defined so far, communication has a number of interesting properties. The first one, which is an immediate consequence of FF , is that communication implies common C belief: C1 £ C w . B w. a This is certainly reasonable when communication is of the assertive type and probably also in a more general context: see Section 2. Instead, the converse implication, B w .C w, is not a theorem of BI , as can be shown by a countermodel; this guarantees a 2 that communication does not merely coincide with common belief. The second important property is that communication is intentional. From FF , FF , C B and E we derive that £C w .B I C w, from which, by the theorem £B I w .I w B a a a a a a a Section 3, we derive: C2 £ C w . I C w. a a a The converse implication, I C w .C w, is not a theorem of BI ; hence, the intention to a a a 2 communicate, by itself, is not sufficient to realize communication. A third property is that communication is public; that is: C3 £ C w . B C w. a E a This is a consequence of F , through the theorem £B w .B B w. From C3 we then C E derive by induction that: M . Colombetti Mathematical Social Sciences 38 1999 171 –196 187 C39 £ C w . B C w. a a In this case, the converse implications hold: C4 £ B C w . C w. E a a C49 £ B C w . C w. a a Theorem C4 is a consequence of F , through the theorem £B B w .B w, and C49 is a C E direct consequence of C4. Property C4 is very interesting, because it shows that there is nothing really ‘objective’ in communication: if all agents individually believe that communication takes place, then communication does actually take place. It is also possible to show that C w is the weakest statement in BI that implies a 2 mutual belief that w, and is both intentional and public. That is, if there is a statement c for which the following theorems can be proved: £ c . B w, £ c . I c, a £ c . B c, E then it follows that: £ c . C w. a We can restate this condition in the form of a derived inference rule: c . B w, c . I c, c . B c a E ]]]]]]]] C5 . c . C w a To prove the validity of C5, it is sufficient to remark that if c satisfies the assumption of C5, then it also satisfies the assumption of RI apply RI to c .B c, and the C B E monotonicity property of B to c .I c. We have now an interesting alternative a characterization of communication: in BI , C w is the weakest intentional and public 2 a statement that implies the common belief that w. The fact that communication is intentional suggests that the statement C w describes a some kind of action. However, a sentence of the form C w need not by itself describe a a 12 basic action. In general, to communicate that w one has to perform some lower-level action c that realizes C w; typically, c will be some action conventionally expressing a a meaning, like raising one’s hand, or ringing a bell, or uttering a sentence in a natural language. We now face a fundamental problem: under what conditions does a lower- level action realize a communicative act? One such a set of conditions is shown by rule C5: an intentional statement describes a w-communicative act if it is public and it implies the common belief that w. However, 12 A basic action is an action that can be performed immediately, with no need of a lower-level action to realize it. Examples of basic actions are raising one’s arm and emitting a sequence of vocal sounds. 188 M . Colombetti Mathematical Social Sciences 38 1999 171 –196 we can prove the validity of a more interesting inference rule, which I shall call the rule of communication: c . I c, c . B w ∧ c a E ]]]]]]] RC . c . C w a The derivation of RC is immediate: From c .B w ∧ c we derive through RI that E C c .B w ∧ c. From this and c .I c, we then derive that c .B w ∧ I c, and from this a a we derive by RI that c .C w. C a The rule of communication can be paraphrased as follows: a sufficient condition for an intentional statement c to describe a w-communicative act is that c is public and displays w. Now we can go back to the problem I have put forward in Section 1: how can agents infer communication from individual beliefs? The answer comes by combining RC with C4 exploiting the monotonicity of B ; we thus derive the inference E rule: c . I c, c . B w ∧ c a E ]]]]]]] RC9 , B c . C w E a which says that if an intentional statement c is public and displays w, for w to be communicated it is sufficient that the speaker and all agents in the audience individually believe that c is performed. This rule gives a possible solution to the problem of inferring communication from individual beliefs.

7. Discussion